This conservative
aesthetic had scientific roots. The psychology of the time continued
to see our senses as perfect reflections of the outside world. The
eye was like a camera: it collected pixels of light and sent them
passively on to the brain. The founder of this psychology was the
eminent experimentalist William Wundt, who insisted that every
sensation could be broken down into its simpler sense data. Science
could peel back the layers of consciousness and reveal the honest
stimuli underneath.
Cezanne inverted this view
of vision. His paintings were about the subjectivity of sight, the
illusion of surfaces. Cezanne invented postimpressionism because the
impressionists just weren't strange enough. "What I am trying to
translate," Cezanne said, "is more mysterious; it is entwined in the
very roots of being." Monet and Renoir and Degas believed that sight
was simply the sum of its light. In their pretty paintings they
wanted to describe the fleeting photons absorbed by the eye, to
describe nature entirely in terms of its illumination. But Cezanne
believed that light was only the beginning of seeing. "The eye is
not enough," he declared. "One needs to think as well." Cezanne's
epiphany was that our impressions require interpretation; to look is
to create what you see.
We now know that Cezanne
was right. Our vision begins with photons, but this is only the
beginning. Whenever we open our eyes, the brain engages in an act of
astonishing imagination, as it transforms the residues of light into
a world of form and space that we can understand. By probing inside
the skull, scientists can see how our sensations are created, how
the cells of the visual cortex silently construct sight. Reality is
not out there waiting to be witnessed; reality is made by the mind.
Cezanne's art exposes the
process of seeing. Although his paintngs were criticized for being
unnecessarily abstract — even the impressionists ridiculed his
technique — they actually show us the world as it first appears to
the brain. A Cezanne picture has no boundaries or stark black lines
separating one thing from the next. Instead, there are only strokes
of paint, and places on the canvas where one color, knotted on the
surface, seems to change into another color. This is the start of
vision: it is what reality looks like beore it has been resolved
by the brain. The light has not yet been made into form.
But Cezanne did not stop
there. That would have been too easy. Even as his art celebrates its
strangeness, it remains loyal to what it represents. As a result, we
can always recognize Cezanne's subjects. Because he gives the brain
just enough information, viewers are able to decipher his paintings
and rescue the picture from the edge of obscurity. (His forms might
be fragile, but they are never incoherent.) The layers of
brushstrokes, so precise in their ambiguity, become a bowl of
peaches, or a granite mountain, or a self-portrait.
This is Cezanne's genius:
he forces us to see, in the same static canvas, the beginning and
the end of our sight. What starts as an abstract mosaic of color
becomes a realistic description. The painting emerges, not from the
paint or the light, but from somewhere inside our mind. We have
entered into the work of art: its strangeness is our own.
Cezanne never lived to see
culture and science catch up with his avant-garde. He was a
postimpressionist before impressionism was fully accepted. But for
Fry and Woolf, Cezanne's style seemed prophetically modern. In the
autumn of 1912, six years after Cezanne died alone in Provence, Fry
mounted the second postimpressionist exhibition at the Grafton
Gallery. Cezanne's paintings were now seen as the start of a serious
movement; his artistic experiments were no longer lonely. The white
walls also displayed canvases by Matisse; the New Russians; and
Virginia's sister, Vanessa Bell. Abstraction had become the new
realism.
The Invention of the
Photograph
The story of abstract
painting begins with the photograph, which literally means "light
writing." That's what a photograph is: an image written in frozen
light. Ever since the Renaissance, artists have used camera obscuras
("dark rooms") to condense the three planes of reality into two
dimensions. Leonardo da Vinci described the instrument in his
notebooks as a metaphor for the eye. Giovanni Battista Delia Porta,
in his 1558 treatise Magia Naturalis (Natural Magic),
advocated the camera as a tool for struggling painters.
But it wasn't until the
nineteenth century, with the discovery of photosensitive chemicals,
that painting lost its monopoly on representation. Verisimilitude
was now a technology. Louis Daguerre, a commercial painter, was the
inventor of the photographic plate. By treating silver-coated copper
sheets with iodine, Daguerre created a flat surface sensitive to
light. He then exposed these plates in a primitive camera (a black
box with a hole) and developed the images with the warm poison of
mercury vapor. The pixels emerged like accurate ghosts. By immersing
the plate in a salt solution, Daguerre made the ghosts permanent.
Light had been captured.
Painters, still in the
business of copying reality, saw the new technology as a dire
threat. How could the human hand compete with the photon? J.M.W.
Turner is said to have remarked after seeing a daguerreotype that he
was glad he'd already had his day, since the era of painting was now
over. But not all artists believed in the inevitable triumph of the
camera. The symbolist poet Charles Baudelaire, a natural skeptic of
science, reviewed a photographic exhibition in 1859 by proclaiming
the limits of the new medium. Its accuracy, he said, is deceptive,
nothing more than phony simulacra of what was really out there. The
photographer was even — and Baudelaire only used this insult in
matters of grave import — a materialist. In Baudelaire's
romantic view, the true duty of photography was "to be the servant
of the sciences and arts, but the very humble servant, like printing
or shorthand, which have neither created nor supplemented
literature.... If it [photography] is allowed to encroach upon the
domain of the imaginary, upon anything whose value depends solely
upon the addition of something of a man's soul, then it will be so
much the worse for us." Baudelaire wanted the modern artist to
describe everything that the photograph ignored: "the transient,
the fleeting, the contingent."
Inspired by Baudelaire's
writings and the provocative realism of Edouard Manet, a motley
group of young French painters decided to rebel. The camera, they
believed, was a liar. Its precision was false. Why? Because reality
did not consist of static images. Because the camera stops time,
which cannot be stopped; because it renders everything in focus,
when everything is never in focus. Because the eye is not a lens,
and the brain is not a machine.
These rebels called
themselves the impressionists. Like the film in a camera, their
idiom was light. But the impressionists realized that light was both
a dot and a blur. If the camera captured the dot, the impressionists
represented the blur. They wanted to capture time in their
paintings, showing how a bale of hay changes in the afternoon
shadows, or how the smoke of a train leaving Gare Saint-Lazare
slowly fades into thin air. As Baudelaire insisted, they painted
what the camera left out.
Look, for example, at an
early Monet, Impression: Soleil Levant (Impression: Sunrise).
Monet painted this hazy scene of the Le Havre harbor in the spring
of 1872. An orange sun hangs in a gray sky; a lonely fisherman sails
in a sea made of undulating brushstrokes. There is little here for
the eye to see. Monet is not interested in the ships, or in their
billowing sails, or in the glassy water. He ignores all the static
things a photograph would detect. Instead, Monet is interested in
the moment, in its transience, in his impression of its transience.
His mood is mixed in with the paint, his subjectivity muddled with
the facts of his sensations. This, he seems to be saying, is a scene
no photograph could catch.

With time, the
impressionists grew more radical. This was partly due to eye
troubles: Monet became blind (but didn't stop painting
the bridges of
Giverny). Vincent van Gogh, drinker of kerosene, turpentine, and
absinthe, probably thought the coronas he painted around stars and
streetlamps were real. Edgar Degas became severely myopic, which
led him to do more and more sculpture ("I must learn a blind man's
trade now," Degas said). Auguste Renoir, poisoned by his pastel
paints, became a rheumatic cripple.
But whether their
abstraction was motivated by physiology or philosophy, it became
increasingly clear that the impressionists had broken with the staid
traditions of academic realism.
They didn't paint religious heroes or epic battles or portraits of
the royal family. Instead, they continued to paint what they had
always painted: the Sunday picnics of the bourgeoisie and women in
bathtubs and purple lilies floating on light-dappled water. When the
critics ridiculed their work as frivolous and false, they just
shrugged. After all, the impressionist art was a celebration of
technique; wherever there was light, they could create paintings.
This is why the
impressionists feel modern, while Delacroix and Ingres and
Bouguereau do not: they realized the painter did not simply have a
subject that he or she was duty bound to represent. The painter was
an artist, and artists had ideas that they were compelled to
express. In their unsellable canvases — the Louvre wouldn't even
accept them as gifts — the impressionists invented the idea of
painterly abstraction. Color became symbolic. Blurriness was chic.
The gaze was out, the glance was in.
But the thing about art
movements is that they are always moving. By freeing the artist
from the strict limits of verisimilitude, impressionism was
destined go places those water lilies could never have imagined. And
if Monet and Degas, prodded by the camera, led the way into
impressionism, Paul Cezanne led the way into its aftermath. As he
immodestly declared at the beginning of his career, "I want to make
of impressionism something solid and lasting, like the art in the
museums."
Cezanne often spent hours
contemplating a brushstroke. Out in the open air, he would stare at
his subject until it melted under his gaze, until the forms of the
world had decayed into a formless mess. By making his vision
disintegrate, Cezanne was trying to return to the start of sight, to
become nothing but "a sensitive recording plate." The slowness of
this method forced Cezanne to focus on simple things, like a few red
apples set on a trapezoid of table, or a single mountain seen from
afar. But he knew that the subject itself was irrelevant. Stare
hard enough, his paintings implore, and the laws of the known
universe will emerge from just about anything. "With an apple,"
Cezanne once said, "I will astonish Paris."
The founder of
postimpressionism learned to paint from a quintessential
impressionist: Camille Pissarro. The two made an incongruous pair.
Pissarro was a French Creole Jew from the West Indies, while Cezanne
was a coarse — some said crude — Provencal. Their friendship was
founded upon their shared sense of isolation. Both were exiles from
the academic style of the time, which had made Ingres into a god and
talent synonymous with fine-grained resolution. Pissarro and
Cezanne had neither the temperament nor the patience for such art.
Pissarro was a friendly anarchist and recommended burning down the
Louvre, while Cezanne — speaking of his early painting instructors —
declared, "Teachers are all castrated bastards and assholes. They
have no guts."
Alone together, Pissarro
and Cezanne saturated themselves in their own style. Cezanne would
methodically copy Pissarro's paintings in order to understand his
impressionist technique. "The eye must absorb everything," Pissarro
instructed him. "Do not follow rules and principles, but paint what
you see and feel. And do not be shy of nature." Cezanne listened to
Pissarro. Before long, the burnt umbers and mahoganies of Cezanne's
early paintings (he loved Courbet) had become the layers of pastel
typical of impressionism. An early work, Rocks at L'Estaque,
depicting Cezanne's favorite Provencal landscape, clearly
demonstrates Pissarro's influence. Staccato brushstrokes
predominate; the colors are basic but exist in myriad tones. Depth
and structure, even the time of day: all are defined by minute
differentiations in the tint of paint. But Rocks at L'Estaque,
for all its impressionist splendor, also shows Cezanne inventing
his own avant-garde.

This is because Cezanne
had stopped worshipping light. He found the impressionist project —
the description of light's dance upon the eye — too insubstantial.
("Monet is only an eye," Cezanne once said, with more than a little
condescension.) In the Rocks at L'Estaque, the sea in the
distance does not sparkle as Pissarro would have had it sparkle. The
granite does not glint in the sunshine, and nothing casts a shadow.
Cezanne was not interested, as the impressionists were, in reducing
everything to surfaces of light. He had stopped arguing with the
camera. Instead, in his postimpressionist paintings he wanted to
reveal how the moment is more than its light. If the
impressionists reflected the eye, Cezanne's art was a mirror held up
to the mind.
What did he see in the
mirror? Cezanne discovered that visual forms — the apple in a still
life or the mountain in a landscape — are mental inventions that we
unconsciously impose onto our sensations. "I tried to copy nature,"
Cezanne confessed, "but I couldn't. I searched, turned, looked at it
from every direction, but in vain." No matter how hard he tried,
Cezanne couldn't escape the sly interpretations of his brain. In
his abstract paintings, Cezanne wanted to reveal this psychological
process, to make us aware of the particular way the mind creates
reality. His art shows us what we cannot see, which is how we see.
The Limits of Light
Understanding how sight
starts, how the eyeball transforms light into an electrical code, is
one of the most satisfying discoveries of modern neuroscience. No
other sense has been so dissected. We now know that vision begins
with an atomic disturbance. Particles of light alter the delicate
molecular structure of the receptors in the retina. This cellular
shudder triggers a chain reaction that ends with a flash of voltage.
The photon's energy has become information.
But that code of light, as
Cezanne knew, is just the start of seeing. If sight were simply the
retina's photoreceptors, then Cezanne's canvases would be nothing
but masses of indistinct color. His Provencal landscapes would
consist of meaningless alternations of olive and ocher, and his
still lifes would be all paint and no fruit. Our
world would be
formless. Instead, in our evolved system, the eyeball's map of
light is transformed again and again until, milliseconds later, the
canvas's description enters our consciousness. Amid the swirl of
color, we see the apple.
What happens during this
blink of unconscious activity? The first scientific glimpse into how
the brain processes the eye's data arrived in the late 1950s, in an
astonishing set of experiments by David Hubel and Torsten Wiesel.
At the time, neuroscience had no idea what kind of visual stimuli
the cortex responded to. Light excites the retina, but what kind of
visual information excites the mind? The experiments attempting to
answer this question were brutally simple: points of light were
flashed onto an animal's retina (a poor cat was usually used) while
a galvanic needle recorded cellular electricity from a brain region
called the V1, which is the first stage of our visual cortex. If
some voltage was detected, then the cell was seeing something.
Before Hubel and Weisel, scientists assumed that the eye was like a
camera, and that the brain's visual field was composed of dots of
light, neatly arranged in time and space. Just as a photograph was
made up of a quilt of pixels, so must the eye create a
two-dimensional representation of reflected light that it seamlessly
transmitted to the brain. Yet when scientists tried finding this
camera inside the skull, all they found was silence, the electrical
stupor of uninterested cells.
This was a frustrating
paradox. The animal clearly could see, and yet its cells, when
isolated with a beam of light, were quiet. It was as if the animal's
vision was emerging from a blank canvas. Hubel and Weisel bravely
ventured into this mystery. At first, their results only confirmed
the impossibility of activating cortical neurons with individual
pricks of light. But then, by complete accident, they discovered an
excited cell, a neuron interested in the slice of world it had
seen.
What was this cell
responding to? Hubel and Weisel had no idea. The neuron became
active at the exact moment it was supposed to be silent, when they
were in between experiments. There was no light to excite it. Only
after retracing their exact steps did Hubel and
Wiesel figure out what had happened. As
they had inserted a glass slide into the light projector, they had
inadvertently cast "a faint but sharp shadow" onto the cat's retina.
It was just a fleeting glint of brightness
— a straight line pointed
in a single direction — but it was exactly what the cell wanted.
Hubel and Wiesel were
stunned by their discovery. They had glimpsed the raw material of
vision, and it was completely abstract. Our brain cells were
strange things, fascinated not by dots of light but by angles of
lines.
These neurons preferred contrast over
brightness, edges over curves. In their seminal 1959 paper
"Receptive Fields of Single Neurons in the Cat's Striate Cortex,"
Hubel and Wiesel became the first scientists to describe reality as
it appears to the early layers of the visual cortex. This is what
the world looks like before it has been seen, when the mind is still
creating the sense of sight.
Cezanne's paintings echo
this secret geometry of lines sensed by the visual cortex. It's as
if he broke the brain apart and saw how seeing occurs. Look, for
example, at The Rocks Above the Caves at Chateau Noir
(1904-1906).

Cezanne has chosen a typically simple subject, just a
few boulders surrounded by some scraggly trees. Windows of blue sky
break through the foliage. But Cezanne's painting is not about the
sky or the rocks or the trees. He has broken each of these elements
into their sensory parts, deconstructing the scene in order to show
us how the mind reconstructs it.
At the literal level of
paint, Cezanne represented the landscape as nothing but a quilt of
brushstrokes, each one a separate line of color. He abandoned the
pointillism of Seurat and Signac, in which everything is dissected
into discrete points of light. Instead, Cezanne pursued a much more
startling path, creating the entire picture out of patches and
strokes, les taches and les touches. His impasto paint
calls attention to itself, forcing us to see the canvas as a
constructive process and not a fixed image. As the art historian
Meyer Schapiro noted, in a Cezanne painting "it is as if there is no
independent, closed, pre-existing object, given to the painter's eye
for representation, but only a multiplicity of successively probed
sensations." Instead of giving us a scene of fully realized forms,
Cezanne supplies us with layers of suggestive edges, out of which
forms slowly unfurl. Our vision is made of lines, and Cezanne has
made the lines distressingly visible.
This is the abstract
reality represented by the neurons of the V1. As the surface of
Cezanne's painting testifies, our most elemental level of sensation
is replete with contradiction and confusion. The cells of the visual
cortex, flooded by rumors of light, see lines extending in every
possible direction. Angles intersect, brushstrokes disagree, and
surfaces are hopelessly blurred together. The world is still
formless, nothing but a collage of chromatic blocks. But this
ambiguity is an essential part of the seeing process, as it leaves
space for our subjective interpretations. Our human brain is
designed so that reality cannot resolve itself. Before we can make
sense of Cezanne's abstract landscape, the mind must intervene.
So far, the story of sight
has been about what we actually sense: the light and lines detected
by the retina and early stages of the visual cortex. These are our
feed-forward projections. They represent the external world of
reflected photons. And while seeing begins with these impressions,
it quickly moves beyond their vague suggestions. After all, the
practical human brain is not interested in a camera-like truth; it
just wants the scene to make sense. From the earliest levels of
visual processing in the brain up to the final polished image,
coherence and contrast are stressed, often at the expense of
accuracy.
Neuroscientists now know
that what we end up seeing is highly influenced by something called
top-down processing, a term that describes the way cortical brain
layers project down and influence (corrupt, some might say) our
actual sensations. After the inputs of the eye enter the brain, they
are immediately sent along two separate pathways, one of which is
fast and one of which is slow. The fast pathway quickly transmits a
coarse and blurry picture to our prefrontal cortex, a brain region
involved in conscious thought. Meanwhile, the slow pathway takes a
meandering route through the visual cortex, which begins
meticulously analyzing and refining the lines of light. The slow
image arrives in the prefrontal cortex about fifty milliseconds
after the fast image.
Why does the mind see
everything twice? Because our visual cortex needs help. After the
prefrontal cortex receives its imprecise picture, the "top" of the
brain quickly decides what the "bottom" has seen and begins
doctoring the sensory data. Form is imposed onto the formless rubble
of the V1; the outside world is forced to conform to our
expectations. If these interpretations are removed, our reality
becomes unrecognizable. The light just isn't enough.
The neurologist Oliver
Sacks once had a patient, Dr. P, who inhabited a world that looked
like a Cezanne canvas. Due to a cortical lesion, Dr. P's eyes
received virtually no input from his brain. He saw the world solely
in its unprocessed form, as labyrinths of light and masses of color.
In other words, he saw reality as it actually was. Unfortunately,
this meant that his sensations were completely surreal. To explore
his patient's illness, Sacks asked Dr. P to describe some
photographs in National Geographic:
"His [Dr. P's] responses
here were very curious. His eyes would dart from one thing to
another, picking up tiny features, individual features, as they had
done with my face. A striking brightness, a colour, a shape would
arrest his attention and elicit comment — but in no case did he get
the scene-as-a-whole. He had no sense whatever of a landscape or
scene."
Dr. P's problem lay in
what happened to the light once it traveled beyond his retina. His
eyes were fine; they were absorbing photons perfectly. It was only
because his brain couldn't interpret his sensations that he saw the
world as such a hopeless commotion of fragments. A photograph seemed
abstract. He couldn't recognize his own reflection. Sacks describes
what happened when Dr. P got up to leave his office: "He [Dr. P]
then started to look round for his hat. He reached out his hand, and
took hold of his wife's head, tried to lift it off, to put it on. He
had apparently mistaken his wife for a hat! His wife looked as if
she was used to such things."
Sacks' tragicomic vignette
exposes an essential element of the seeing process. One of the
functions of top-down processing is object recognition. The
instructions of the prefrontal cortex allow us to assimilate the
different elements of an object — all those lines and edges seen by
the V1 — into a unified concept of the object. This was what
Dr. P couldn't do. His impressions of light never congealed into a
thing. As a result, before Dr. P could "see" a glove, or his left
foot, or his wife, he had to painstakingly decipher his own
sensations. Every form needed to be methodically analyzed, as if it
were being seen for the first time. For example, when Dr. P was
given a rose, he described his conscious thought process to Sacks:
"It looks about six inches in length. A convoluted red form with a
linear green attachment." But these accurate details never triggered
the idea of a rose. Dr. P had to smell the flower before he could
identify its form. As Sacks put it, "Dr. P saw nothing as familiar.
Visually, he was lost in a world of lifeless abstractions."
To look at a Cezanne
painting is to become acutely aware of what Dr. P is missing.
Staring at his postimpressionist art, we feel our top-down process
at work. It is because Cezanne knew that the impression was not
enough — that the mind must complete the impression — that
he created a style both more abstract and more truthful than the
impressionists. And even though his postimpressionist style was
seen as needlessly radical — Manet referred to him as "the
bricklayer who paints with a trowel" — it wasn't. Cezanne abstracted
on nature because he realized that everything we see is an
abstraction. Before we can make sense of our sensations, we have to
impress our illusions upon them.
In his art, Cezanne made
this mental process self-evident. While he deconstructed his
paintings until they were on the verge of unraveling, his paintings
don't unravel, and that is their secret. Instead, they tremble on
the edge of existence, full of fractures and fissures that have to
be figured out. Such an exquisite balancing act isn't easy. Until
Cezanne sold a canvas — and he rarely sold anything — he continued
to edit his brushstrokes, trying to edge closer to the delicate
reality he wanted to describe. His work would become thick with
paint, with layer after layer of carefully applied color. Then the
paint would crack, broken by its own mass.
Why was painting such a
struggle for Cezanne? Because he knew that a single false
brushstroke could ruin his canvas. Unlike the impressionists, who
wanted their paintings to reflect the casual atmospherics of being
en plein air, Cezanne's art was adamantly difficult. In his
clenched canvases, he wanted to give the brain just enough to
decipher, and not a brushstroke more. If his representations were
too accurate or too abstract, everything fell apart. The mind would
not be forced to enter the work of art. His lines would have no
meaning.
Cezanne and Zola
The year was 1858. Cezanne
was eighteen. His best friend, Emile Zola, had just left for Paris,
leaving him behind in Aix-en-Provence. Zola had already decided to
become a writer, but Cezanne, following the demands of his
authoritarian father, was busy failing out of law school. Zola was
furious with Cezanne. "Is painting only a whim for you?" he angrily
asked. "Is it only a pastime, a subject of conversation? If this is
the case, then I understand your conduct: you are right not to make
trouble with your family. But if painting is your vocation, then you
are an enigma to me, a sphinx, someone impossible and obscure." The
very next summer, Cezanne fled to Paris. He had decided to become an
artist.
Life in the city was
difficult. Cezanne was lonely and impoverished. Being a bohemian was
overrated. During the day, he sneaked into the Louvre, where he
patiently copied works by Titian and Rubens. At night, everyone
crowded into the local bar and drunkenly argued about politics and
art.
Cezanne felt like a
failure. His first experiments in abstraction were dismissed as
accidental mistakes, the feeble work of a talentless realist. He
carted his paintings around the city in a wheelbarrow, but no
gallery would accept them. Cezanne's only consolation lay in the
culture at large: the stuffy Parisian art world was finally
beginning to change. Baudelaire had begun assailing Ingres. Manet
was studying Velazquez. The gritty paintings of Gustave Courbet —
his mantra was "Let us be true, even if we are ugly" — were slowly
gaining respect.
By 1863, all of this new
"ugliness" could no longer be suppressed. There was simply too much
of it. As a result, Emperor Napoleon III decided to exhibit the
paintings rejected by the Academy of Fine Arts for their annual art
show. It was in this gallery — the Salon of the Refused — that
Cezanne would first glimpse Manet's Le Dejeuner sur I'Herbe (The
Luncheon on the Grass), a scandalous picture of a naked woman in
a park who doesn't seem to know she's naked.

Cezanne was mesmerized.
He began a series of paintings in which he reimagined Manet's
pornographic picnic. Unlike Manet, who painted the woman with a
sense of ironic detachment, Cezanne inserted himself into the
middle of the artwork. His scraggly beard and bald head give him
away. The same critics that had been disdainful of Manet were now
cruel to Cezanne. "The public sneers at this art," wrote one
reviewer. "Mr. Cezanne gives the impression of being a sort of
madman who paints in delirium tremens. He must stop
painting."
.jpg)
Twenty years later,
everything had changed. The emperor was gone, defeated in battle
during the Franco-Prussian War. Claude Monet, who fled Paris in
order to avoid serving in the army, had glimpsed the prophetically
abstract watercolors of J.M.W. Turner while in London. He returned
to France newly inspired. By 1885, Monet's impressionism was a
genuine avant-garde. The painters of hazy light now had their own
salons.
The intervening years had
also been kind to Zola. His Rougon-Macquart novels turned him into a
literary celebrity, confidently controversial. He was the proud
founder of naturalism, a new school of literature that aspired to
write "the scientific novel." The novelist, Zola declared, must
literally become a scientist, "employing the experimental method in
their study of man."
Flush with his success,
Zola decided to write a book about a painter. He called it
L'Oeuvre (The Masterpiece) because he said he could think of
nothing better. As required by his method, Zola based his fiction on
a story stolen straight from real life. The life he stole this time
was the life of his best friend. After the novel was published, in
the spring of 1886, Cezanne and Zola never spoke to each other
again.
The protagonist of The
Masterpiece is Claude Lantier. Like Cezanne, he is a bearded and
balding Provencal, a painter whose paintings are too strange to
display. Zola even got the afflictions right: both Claude and Paul
suffer from incurable eye diseases, are ridiculed by their fathers,
and have to trade their paintings for food at the local grocery.
While Claude is the stereotypical struggling artist, his best
friend, the thinly veiled writer Pierre Sandoz, has achieved great
literary acclaim, writing a series of twenty novels documenting
"the truth of humanity in miniature."
But the real insult came
when Zola described Claude's art. His abstract paintings, Zola
wrote, were nothing but "wild mental activity . . . the terrible
drama of a mind devouring itself." Sandoz's novels, on the other
hand, "describe man as he really is." They are a "new literature for
the coming century of science."
It was clear that Zola had
betrayed his impressionist friends. Monet, Pissarro, and the
symbolist poet Stephane Mallarme held meetings to denounce the book.
"Our enemies," Monet wrote to Zola, "will make use of your book to
cudgel us senseless." But Zola
didn't care. He had turned
against abstraction. If Cezanne's paintings made our subjectivity
their subject, Zola's novels were determined to turn man into just
another object. The artist, Zola said, must "disappear, and simply
show what he has seen. The tender intervention of the writer
weakens a novel, and introduces a strange element into the facts
which destroys their scientific value."
Zola's style didn't last
long. His self-proclaimed scientific novels, with their naive faith
in heredity and biological determinism, aged ungracefully. His work
was not the "immortal encyclopedia of human truths" he had expected
it to become. As Oscar Wilde declared, "Zola sits down to give us a
picture of the Second Empire. Who cares for the Second Empire now?
It is out of date. Life goes faster than Realism." Even worse, the
avant-garde that Zola betrayed in The Masterpiece was now
ascendant. His movement was being usurped by postimpressionism. By
1900, Zola was forced to admit that he had misjudged Cezanne's
abstract art. "I have a better understanding of his painting," Zola
confessed, "which eluded me for a long time because I thought it was
exaggerated, but actually it is unbelievably sincere and truthful."
In the end, it was not
The Masterpiece that drove Cezanne and Zola apart. Zola never
apologized, but it was just as well: no apology could heal the rift
in their philosophies. They were two childhood friends who had come
to conflicting conclusions about the nature of reality. If Zola
tried to escape himself in his art — fleeing instead into the cold
realm of scientific fact — Cezanne sought reality by venturing
into himself. He knew that the mind makes the world, just as a
painter makes a painting.
With that startling
revelation, Cezanne invented modernist art. His canvases were
deliberately new; he broke the laws of painting in order to reveal
the laws of seeing. If he left some details out, it was only to show
us what we put in. Within a few decades, of course, Paris would be
filled with a new generation of modern painters who liked to break
the law even more. The cubists, led by Pablo Picasso and Georges
Braque, would take Cezanne's technique to its incongruous
conclusion. (Picasso once declared that Cezanne and Buffalo Bill
were his two greatest influences.) And even though the cubists liked
to joke about anticipating the weird facts of quantum physics, no
other painter got the human mind like Cezanne. His abstractions
reveal our anatomy.
The Blank Canvas
As Cezanne aged, his
paintings became filled by more and more naked canvas, what he
eloquently called nonfinito. No one had ever done this
before. The painting was clearly incomplete. How could it be art?
But Cezanne was unfazed by his critics. He knew that his paintings
were only literally blank.
Their incompleteness was really a metaphor for the process of
sight. In these unfinished canvases, Cezanne was trying to figure
out what the brain would finish for him. As a result, his
ambiguities are exceedingly deliberate, his vagueness predicated on
precision. If Cezanne wanted us to fill in his empty spaces, then he
had to get his emptiness exactly right.
For example, look at
Cezanne's watercolors of Mont Sainte-Victoire. In his final years,
Cezanne walked every morning to the crest of Les Lauves, where an
expansive view of the Provencal plains opened up before him. He
would paint in the shade of a linden tree. From there, Cezanne said,
he could see the land's hidden patterns, the way the river and
vineyards were arranged in overlapping planes. In the background was
always the mountain, that jagged isosceles of rock that seemed to
connect the dry land with the infinite sky.

Cezanne, of course, was
not interested in literal portraits of the landscape. In his
descriptions of the valley, Cezanne wanted to paint only the
essential elements, the necessary skeleton of form. And so he
summarized the river in a single swerve of blue. The groves of
chestnut trees became little more than dabs of dull green,
interrupted occasionally by a subtle stroke of umber. And then there
was the mountain. Cezanne often condensed the foreboding mass of
Mont Sainte-Victoire into a single line of dilute paint, dragged
across the empty sky. This thin gray line — the shadowy silhouette
of the mountain — is completely surrounded by negative space. It is
a fragile scratch against the sprawling void.

And yet the mountain does
not disappear. It is there, an implacable and adamant
presence. The mind easily invents the form that Cezanne's paint
barely insinuates. Although the mountain is almost literally
invisible — Cezanne has only implied its presence — its looming
gravity anchors the painting. We don't know where the painting ends
and we begin.
Cezanne's embrace of the
blank canvas — his decision to let the emptiness show through — was
his most radical invention. Unlike the academic style, which
worshipped clarity and decorative detail above all, the subject of
Cezanne's postimpressionist paintings was their own ambiguity. With
their careful confusion of things and nothing, Cezanne's
nonfinito paintings question the very essence of form. His
incomplete landscapes were proof that even when there was no
sensation — the canvas was empty — we could still see. The mountain
was still there.
When Cezanne began his
studies in the blank canvas, science had no way of explaining why
the paintings appeared less vacant than they actually were. The very
existence of Cezanne's nonfinito style, the fact that the
brain could find meaning in nothing, seemed to disprove any theory
of mind that reduced our vision to pixels of light.
The Gestalt psychologists,
of the early twentieth century were the first scientists to confront
the illusions of form that Cezanne so eloquently manipulated.
Gestalt literally means "form," and that's what interested
Gestalt psychologists. Founded by Carl Stumpf, Kurt Koffka, Wolfgang
Kohler, and Max Wertheimer in the beginning of the twentieth
century, the German Gestalt movement began as a rejection of the
reductionist psychology of its time, which was still enthralled with
the theories of Wilhelm Wundt and his fellow psychophysicists. Wundt
had argued that visual perception is ultimately reducible to its
elemental sensations. The mind, like a mirror, reflected light.
But the mind is not
a mirror. The Gestaltists set out to prove that the process of
seeing alters the world we observe. Like Immanuel Kant, their
philosophical precursor, they argued that much of what was thought
of as being out there
—
in our sensations of the outside world — actually came from in
here, from inside the mind. ("The imagination," Kant wrote, "is
a necessary ingredient of perception itself.") As evidence for their
theories of perception, the Gestaltists used optical illusions.
These ranged from the illusion of apparent motion in a movie (the
film is really a set of static photographs flipped twenty-four times
a second) to drawings that seem to oscillate between two different
forms (the classic example is the vase that can also be seen as two
faces in silhouette). According to the Gestaltists, these everyday
illusions were proof that everything we saw was an illusion. Form is
dictated from the top down. Unlike the
Wundtians, who began with
our sensory fragments, the Gestaltists began with reality as we
actually experienced it.
Modern neuroscientific
studies of the visual cortex have confirmed the intuitions of
Cezanne and the Gestaltists: visual experience transcends visual
sensations. Cezanne's mountain arose from the empty canvas because
the brain, in a brazen attempt to make sense of the painting, filled
in its details. This is a necessary instinct. If the mind didn't
impose itself on the eye, then our vision would be full of voids.
For example, because there are no light-sensitive cones where the
optic nerve connects to the retina, we each have a literal blind
spot in the center of the visual field. But we are blind to our own
blind spot: our brain unfailingly registers a seamless world.
This ability to make sense
of our incomplete senses is a result of human cortical anatomy. The
visual cortex is divided into distinct areas, neatly numbered 1
through 5. If you trace the echoes of light from the V1, the neural
area where information from the retina first appears as a collection
of lines, to the V5, you can watch the visual scene acquire its
unconscious creativity. Reality is continually refined, until the
original sensation — that incomplete canvas — is swallowed by our
subjectivity.
The first area in the
visual cortex where neurons respond to both illusory and actual
imagery is the V2. It is here that the top part of the mind begins
altering the lower levels of sight. As a result, we begin to see a
mountain where there is only a thin black line. From this point on,
we can't separate our own mental inventions from what really exists.
The exact same neurons respond when we actually see a mountain and
when we just imagine a mountain. There is no such thing as
immaculate perception.
After being quickly
processed by the other areas of the visual cortex — color and
motion are now integrated into the picture — the data flows into the
medial temporal lobe (also known as V5), the region in the brain
that gives rise to conscious perceptions. In this area near the back
of the head, small subsets of cells first respond to complex
stimuli, such as a Cezanne painting of a mountain, or a real
mountain. When these specific neurons light up, all the visual
processing is finally finished. The sensation is now ready for
consciousness.
And because neurons in the
temporal cortex are very specific in their representations, tiny
lesions in this brain region can erase entire categories of
form. This syndrome is called visual-object agnosia. Some victims
of this syndrome might fail to perceive apples, or faces, or
postimpressionist paintings. Even if the victim maintains an
awareness of the object's various elements, he or she is unable to
bind those fragments into a coherent representation. The point is
that our world of form only exists at this late stage of neural
processing, in cranial folds far removed from the honest light of
the outside world.
Furthermore, the nerves
that feed into consciousness are themselves modulated by
consciousness. Once the prefrontal cortex thinks it has seen a
mountain, it starts adjusting its own inputs, imagining a form in
the blank canvas. (To paraphrase Paul Simon, "A man sees what he
wants to see, and disregards the rest.") In fact, in the lateral
geniculate nucleus (LGN), the thick nerve that connects the eyeball
to the brain, ten times more fibers project from the cortex to the
eye than from the eye to the cortex. We make our eyes lie. As
William James wrote in Pragmatism: "A sensation is rather
like a client who has given his case to a lawyer and then has
passively to listen in the courtroom to whatever account of his
affairs the lawyer finds it most expedient to give."
What is the moral of all
these anatomy lessons? The mind is not a camera. As Cezanne
understood, seeing is imagining. The problem is that there is no way
to quantify what we think we see. Each of us is locked inside
our own peculiar vision. If we removed our self-consciousness from
the world, if we saw with the impersonal honesty of our eyeballs,
then we would see nothing but lonely points of light, glittering in
a formless space. There would be no mountain. The canvas would
simply be empty. The postimpressionist movement begun by Cezanne was
the first
style to make our dishonest
subjectivity its subject. His paintings are criticisms of paintings:
they call attention to their own un-real-ity. A Cezanne painting
admits that the landscape is made of negative space, and that the
bowl of fruit is a collection of brushstrokes. Everything has been
bent to fit the canvas. Three dimensions have been flattened into
two, light has been exchanged for paint, the whole scene has been
knowingly composed. Art, Cezanne reminds us, is surrounded by
artifice.
The shocking fact is that
sight is like art. What we see is not real. It has been bent to fit
our canvas, which is the brain. When we open our eyes, we enter into
an illusory world, a scene broken apart by the retina and re-created
by the cortex. Just as a painter interprets a picture, we interpret
our sensations. But no matter how precise our neuronal maps become,
they will never solve the question of what we actually see, for
sight is a private phenomenon. The visual experience transcends the
pixels of the retina and the fragmentary lines of the visual cortex.
It is art, and not
science, that is the means by which we express what we see on the
inside. The painting, in this respect, is closest to reality. It is
what gets us nearest to experience. When we stare at Cezanne's
apples, we are inside his head. By trying to represent his own
mental representations, Cezanne showed art how to transcend the myth
of realism. As Rainer Maria Rilke wrote, "Cezanne made the fruit so
real that it ceased to be edible altogether, that's how thing like
and real they became, how simply indestructible in their stubborn
thereness." The apples have become what they have always been: a
painting created by the mind, a vision so abstract it seems real.

The stylistic innovations of the impressionists also
depended on developments in paint technology. For example,
the cobalt violet that Monet often used to paint the ocean
and sky had been invented just a few years earlier by
industrial chemists. Monet quickly realized that this new
pigment had enormous potential for describing the effects of
light. "I have finally discovered the color of the
atmosphere," Monet declared. "It is violet."
Emile Bernard, a French painter, was one of the few people
to actually observe Cezanne's painting technique. As he
watched Cezanne construct his canvases, Bernard was struck
by how Cezanne had broken entirely with the rules of
impressionism: "His method was not at all like that...
Cezanne only interpreted what he saw, he did not try to copy
it. His vision was centered much more in his brain, than in
his eye" (Doran, p. 60).
The electrical message of photoreceptors is actually the
absence of an electrical message, as the photons cause the
sodium ion channels inside our photoreceptors to close,
which causes the cell to become hyperpolarized. Eyes speak
with silence.
The early parts of our visual cortex are stimulated by
visual inputs that look very similar to a Piet Mondrian
painting. Mondrian, a painter extremely influenced by
Cezanne, spent his life searching for what he called "the
constant truths concerning forms." He eventually settled on
the straight line as the essence of his art. He was right,
at least from the perspective of the V1.
As Gertrude Stein said of one of these Cezanne landscapes,
"Finished or unfinished, it always was what looked like the
very essence of an oil painting, because everything was
there."